About 'thomas aquinas university'|...his right to teach in Catholic universities on order of the Office for the...and theologians like Thomas Aquinas, Meister Eckhart and Hildegard of...
Science and religion share a tumultuous history. In the secular context of contemporary Western society, science and religion play roles of almost complete opposition: the first consisting of empirical knowledge gathered to prove or disprove; the latter defined by a collective set of beliefs and ritual commitments centered on a common faith. The evolution of the two bodies share greater similarities than differences, commonalities that have significant influence over the Middle and late Middle Ages. During the Renaissance, the dual categories of 'Science' and 'Religion' coexisted as a homogenous entity (although in much different evolutionary forms), instigated by religious motives, used to pursue theological investigation. The Renaissance heralded a rebirth of interest in classical thought, culture, and writing. New appreciations for Greek culture and classics occupied the faculty of Renaissance universities. Aristotelianism, along with the works of Plato, Socrates, Thales found prominence in the universities in Paris, Salerno, Bologna, Padua, Florence, and other cities; inspired the studies of St. Thomas Aquinas, Philip Melanchthon, among others; and excited the disciplines of natural philosophy, medicine, and logic. Intellectuals attempted to explain the plight of the Middle Ages (ie. the Black Death, the Little Ice Age, the Hundred Years War, the collapse of Constantinople, etc.) through classical thought. The Renaissance, however, engendered little in the way of scientific progress-at least in the way of scientific structure. Though some of the research paved the way for the Scientific Revolution, the intellectual culture of the Renaissance, underlined by theology, greatly influenced natural investigation and produced an atmosphere stimulating to scholarly growth yet stunting to scientific advance. [i] The contemporary relationship between science and religion as two independent, often adversarial mechanisms is a relatively young phenomenon. Similarly, the modern forms of the two disciplines little resemble their genealogical ancestors. Historiography plays a significant role in framing this debate. The definitions of the terms "Science," "Religion," and "Natural Philosophy," their evolution over time, and the context in which each respective term exists, are vital to understanding the significance of their variable and contrasting genealogies. The dynamic etymology of the term "science" creates difficulty in establishing a uniform standard of science. The constant nature of change complicates the relationship of different periods in time, perpetuating the "anachronistic assumption that the study of nature in earlier historical periods was prosecuted more or less along the same lines as those adopted by modern scientists."[ii] This potential source of confusion illustrates the difficulty in assigning science an identity. An ambiguity exists between the modern definition and that used during the middle ages. The origins of the term science stem from the Latin, scientia. Scholars used scientia to represent the highest form of knowledge. During Renaissance times, scholars also used scientia to describe the study of theology and natural philosophy, deeming them 'sciences.' The term, when used in this context, obviously cannot be understood to relate to modern definitions of science. This universal application of scientia only helps to obfuscate its meaning. This illustrates the confusion this debate conjures.[iii] Conventional histories of science attribute the Greeks with its conception, and the Scientific Revolution (the later stages), in the nineteenth century, with the origins of the "modern" discipline. The science historian G. E. R. Lloyd contests, however, that, "science is a modern category, not an ancient one: there is no one term that is exactly equivalent to our 'science' in Greek."[iv] Identifying a ubiquitous, uniform definition of science suggests an anachronism. The history of the term implies its tortuous evolution.[v] Although scholars often overlook the interim (between the Greek Hellenistic period and the Scientific Revolution), or consider science of the Middle and Late Middle Ages (during which the Renaissance occurred) inert, this period illustrates a crucial stage in the relationship between science and religion. Between the 1200s and the 1800s, natural philosophy nominally embodied the general practice of science (or the hiatus thereof). Natural philosophy, however, differed in essence from modern science, and existed as a unique apparatus. Scholars believe current perceptions of science originated in the nineteenth century (William Whewell initially coined the term scientist in 1833). Prior to that, men of science (often synonymous with 'men of faith') considered themselves students of 'natural philosophy' or 'natural history,' and practiced a much different form of investigation then their twenty-first-century counterparts. Examining the relationship between science and religion during the Renaissance then leads to a complex conclusion, as Peter Harrison of Bond University illustrates: "This claim has obvious ramifications for those whose concern lies with the past relationship between science and religion, for if it is true, such a relationship cannot be older than the nineteenth century."[vi] With its relatively recent classification as well-during the European Enlightenment-religion, concurrently, provides the same concerns.[vii] Recent debate among science historians over this difference stands to change the conventional view of the history of science. Traditional views pit natural philosophy in line with the direct succession of science, claiming distinctions only in the periods of time, and stages of scientific development. New interpretations dissent from this view, realigning natural philosophy outside of the confines of science. Andrew Cunningham of the University of Cambridge argues that "As a result, we have no histories of natural philosophy as such, only histories of 'medieval science' and of 'early modern science.'"[viii] This presumed continuity ignores the existence of natural philosophy as a distinct discipline, independent of science. In fact, a demarcation existed between the two models. Simon Schaffer posited "The end of natural philosophy was accompanied by the appearance of models of discovery which appealed to discipline and to genius, and which have dominated theories of science ever since."[ix] Similarly, William Whewell argued that the emergence of trained scientists signaled the close of natural philosophy.[x] Philisophia naturalis, or natural philosophy, as demonstrated, differed from science in a multitude of ways. Extant prior to the modern development of science, natural philosophy applied to the objective study of nature and the universe. First constructed by Robert Boyle in 1686, natural philosophy only gained connotation as an entity distinct from science after his death, although modern historians apply it to earlier historical figures. Considered the forerunner of natural science, natural philosophy often operated in conjunction with theology and other philosophical tools. Cunningham characterized it as the study of "God's achievements, God's intentions, God's purposes, God's messages to man."[xi] The divine-humanity of Christ-the simultaneous activity of the two natures-nicely embodies the cognitive juxtaposition evident during this time. Frequently, theological or spiritual questions fueled natural investigation. For example, Charlotte Methuen claims that, "certain formulations of the doctrine of providence, with its assumption that God both created and sustained the world for the good of its human inhabitants; could provide an impulse towards the study of the natural world."[xii] In terms of logic: God created the natural world. A greater understanding of nature provided a greater understanding of God's creation; thus a greater understanding of God. An important distinction between the contemporary concept of science and its Renaissance progenitors reflects science's symbiotic relationship with theology (devoid of course in today's concept). In fact, during the Renaissance, science and theology operated homogeneously (represented by the term natural philosophy), espoused under the genre of natural sciences. The study of natural philosophy incorporated intellectual and philosophical conventions instigated by theological concerns, much in contrast to the modern, secular definition as a systematic arrangement of knowledge of the physical or material world, gained through observation and experimentation, and exhibiting the operation of general laws. The inextricable connection between theology and nature in Renaissance philosophy made it impossible to study either independently. Historians tend to draw on a contemporary base of knowledge when studying science's history. Historian Charles Webster explains that, "Conclusions about the independence of scientific activity...are based not on the impartial and exhaustive examination of evidence, but are rather dictated by the requirements of current ideology, and describe not the relationship which actually existed, but the relationship which it is felt ought to have existed on the basis of present-day opinion about the methodology of science."[xiii] The ability to classify the methods of earlier practitioners as incongruent with modern conventions provides the opportunity to fruitfully explore the relationship between natural philosophy and theology. Congruently, Renaissance students inspired by Aristotle, classified sciences into three "speculative sciences." The speculative sciences included natural science (physics), mathematics, and metaphysics (philosophy or theology).[xiv]. The nineteenth century witnessed science's emergence as a discipline free of theology or religion. This split enabled the relationship between science and religion to exist, although some boundaries tended to blur. But, for the first time, institutions of science employed scientific practitioners independent of clerical influences. Science, as an independent entity espoused a professionalism. The British Association for the Advancement of Science appeared in the 1830s, followed by others. As science professionalized, encompassing the various disciplines of empirical thought, a new set of professional commitments and responsibilities materialized. Increasingly, the clergy reluctantly relinquished the hegemony they held over the wonders of nature. A.W. Benn noted, "A great part of the reverence once given to priests and to their stories of an unseen universe has been transformed to the astronomer, the geologist, the physician, and the engineer."[xv] By the start of the twentieth century, science stood devoid of its former ethical and theological partners. The "wonders of nature" became the "wonders of science." [xvi] Similar to the discourse on the history of science, scholars approximate the foundation of religion, in its modern understanding, to the relatively recent period of the European Enlightenment. Wilfred Cantwell Smith describes the origination, writing, "The concept 'religion,' then, in the West has evolved. Its evolution has included a long-range development that we may term a process of reification: mentally making religion into a thing, gradually coming to conceive it as an objective systematic entity."[xvii] This 'systematic entity' shifted focus from devotion to the search for truth. The characterization also allowed for the comparison of religions, and consequently instigated the science of comparative religion. This practice, which involved the categorization of people and their beliefs, provided a frame of reference for Western securitization. Subsequent to the Age of Discovery, and to the fabrication of 'religion,' Western thought in the nineteenth century recognized the "birth" of other religions: Hinduism, Taoism, Buddhism, and Confucianism; all of which existed much earlier. But the 'creation' of religion allowed for the distinguishment of unique bodies of faith.[xviii] The nineteenth century, as it represented the emergence of science as an independent entity, also recognized religion as an institution free of science. With science and religion both autonomous entities, the urge to perpetuate the existence of conflict between the two became attractive. Advocates of the nascent scientific movement saw the political benefit of pitting their cause against the hegemonic institution of the Church, giving birth to the science-religion apposition myth. This myth claims that a fundamental rift between the institutions existed and has fomented over the course of this tenuous relationship. Whether extant during the nascent stages of the relationship or not, the two institutions clearly evolved into separate entities, independent of the other, and sometimes occupying positions of opposition. The development of theology, neglected so far, also played an important role in the science/religion discussion. As with these previous terms, the relatively young "theology" appeared as a new discipline during the Renaissance. First appearing in Plato's Republic, the term is a combination of theos, meaning god, and logos, meaning rational utterance, and defined as reasoned discourse about God. Modern theologians study the history of religion, religious thought, or religious traditions; defend doctrines or compare religious traditions. During the Renaissance, in the burgeoning university system, theology too fell under the auspice of science. It produced firm knowledge (science), prompting scholars to consider it a rational object (obviously a contradiction in today's terms, but which makes sense when considering this developmental stage of theology relied on reason rather than on faith). This sense still, however, conflicts with the modern usage of the term.[xix] Histories of science scholars often use theology interchangeable with religion. The terms, however, are not synonymous. The first espouses the characteristics of a discipline, or mechanism. The latter, a term which comes along much later and that describes an objective systematic entity. The birth of theology as a discipline signaled an interest in the objective study of God in the state of scientific discovery during this time. This context provided a nonbelligerent atmosphere for theology to achieve its purpose. Mirroring the evolution of the relationship between science and religion, theology transformed from a scientific discipline involved in the investigation of God and nature to one completely devoid of science, preoccupied with the pursuit of truth through scripture and the study of religion. During the Renaissance, theologies function coincided with that of the relationship of science and religion in natural philosophy. The trinity of these concepts comprised the unique confluence of this period. The Renaissance distinguished itself by creating an atmosphere amicable to the confluence of religion, science, and theology. The harmony of these three ideas, although short lived, made possible the growth and emergence of each as independent entities. This harmony of these three ideas, although short lived, made possible the growth and emergence of each as independent entities. This harmony, the product of an intersection of classical thought and Christian hegemony-altogether impossible in contemporary Western society-becomes unsurprising when considered in the context of an epoch dominated by the Catholic Church. The picture becomes clearer also with the understanding of the evolution of these three entities. The push towards recognition of natural philosophy, its importance, and its distinction from the modern concept of science may provide a demystification of the conflict between science and religion and the ambiguous nature of scientific history. 'Science' and 'Religion,' during the Renaissance coexisted as a homogenous entity in natural philosophy, and functioned as a tool of theological investigation. This state of homogeneity prevented a relationship between the two, however, until he establishment of science and religion as separate entities-in the seventeenth and nineteen centuries, respectively-allowed a relationship to establish. The emergence of their independence also signaled fundamental changes in their functions and orientations. These fundamental changes precipitated the foundation of their modern decedents, and complicated their historical discourse. Although often overlooked in the history of science, the Renaissance stands as a unique confluence of ideas beneficial to the comprehension of the Middle and late Middle Ages. Notes [i] Lewis W. Spitz, The Renaissance and Reformation Movements, Vol. 1 (St. Louis: 1987): 180; Herbert Butterfield, The Origins of Modern Science (New York: 1960): 37. [ii] Peter Harrison, "'Science' and 'Religion': Constructing the Boundaries," Journal of Religion, Vol. 86, No. 1 (Jan. 2006): 82. [iii] Andrew Cunningham, "The Identity of Natural Philosophy. A Response to Edward Grant," Early Science and Medicine, Vol. 5, No. 3. (2000): 260. [iv] G. E. R. Lloyd, Early Greek Science (New York: Norton, 1970), iv. [v] Harrison, 82. [vi] Harrison, 81. [vii] Harrison, 86. [viii] Cunningham, 260. [ix] Simon Schaffer, "Scientific Discoveries and the End of Natural Philosophy," Social Studies of Science, Vol. 16, No. 3. (Aug., 1986): 407. [x] Whewell, William, History of the Inductive Sciences from the Earliest to the Present Time V2 (London: 2006): 16. [xi] Andrew Cunningham, "Getting the Game Right: Some Plain Words on the Identity and Invention of Science," Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 19 (1988): 365. [xii] Methuen, Charlotte, "Lex Naturae And Ordo Naturae in the Thought of Philip Melanchthon," Reformation & Renaissance Review: Journal of the Society for Reformation Studies, Iss. 3 (2000): 111. [xiii] Charles Webster, The Great Instauration: Science, Medicine, and Reform, 1626-1660 (London: 1975), 494; The discussion on the term scientia are taken from: Cunningham, "The Identity of Natural Philosophy. A Response to Edward Grant,"260-261. [xiv] Robert W. Schmidt, S.J., The Domain of Logic According to Saint Thomas Aquinas (The Hague, 1966): 16-18. [xv] A. W. Benn, A History of English Rationalism in the Nineteenth Century, 2 vols. (London: Longmans, Green, & Todd, 1906), 1:198. Cited in: Harrison, 88. [xvi] Harrison, 87. [xvii] Harrison, 91. [xviii] Harrison, 92-93. [xix] Cunningham, 260-261. |
Image of thomas aquinas university
thomas aquinas university Image 1
thomas aquinas university Image 2
thomas aquinas university Image 3
thomas aquinas university Image 4
thomas aquinas university Image 5
Related blog with thomas aquinas university
- catholicwritings.blogspot.com/Popular University of St. Thomas Aquinas The ...TITLE : The Popular University of St. Thomas Aquinas For Human ...this popular university is to...
- virtueamonth.blogspot.com/...conversion to Catholicism. So Edith lectured at the University of Munster, translated works of Thomas Aquinas and John Cardinal Newman. "She successfully combined...
- unafraidcatholic.wordpress.com/...the ritual. I then wrote this response about the candlelight Mass at my parish, St. Thomas Aquinas University Parish, in Boulder. The Lord used this liturgy to gently pull me back to...
- herecomeseverybody.blogspot.com/...I was a freshman at a public university, I took a graduate seminar with... of independent study on Thomas Aquinas and scholasticism with a brilliant Dominican...
- chezodysseus.blogspot.com/...can see, there’s a lot that can be discussed. NOTES *New London: Yale University Press. ISBN: 978-0-300-15179-4 **The reality that the English “love” cannot adequately convey...
- rougeknights.blogspot.com/...Indian dreams. It was a university town and the whole issue of ... me reading Thomas Aquinas , G.K Chesterton and so forth. So the...
- talesofthenewworld.blogspot.com/...winter evenings round the fire on the open hearth. Peter Maverick had no University degree. That omission was rectified in the education of his son. There...
- zengersmag.blogspot.com/...his right to teach in Catholic universities on order of the Office for the...and theologians like Thomas Aquinas, Meister Eckhart and Hildegard of...
- markalburgermusichistory.blogspot.com/...censure in the history of the University of Paris, and a landmark in... many years for Thomas's reputation to recover from...Second Council of Lyons. Aquinas's task was to investigate...
- darwinianconservatism.blogspot.com/... that Straussian analysis is a paper by Thomas G. West (of the University of Dallas)--"Thomas Aquinas on Natural Law: A Critique of the 'Straussian' Critique." This long paper (100...
Thomas Aquinas University - Blog Homepage Results
... to the problems which Thomas faced, and partly solved, that we...its unity." -- Wayne J. Hankey, God in Himself (Oxford University Press, 1987), p.159.
Related Video with thomas aquinas university
thomas aquinas university Video 1
thomas aquinas university Video 2
thomas aquinas university Video 3
0 개의 댓글:
댓글 쓰기